The Philosophy of the Implicit
An Introduction
to the Work of Gene Gendlin
Robert
Parker, PhD
Beginnings
The
Philosophy of the Implicit is a new way of thinking which reunites science and spirituality, carrying each forward in new
and exciting ways. Although the core concepts are very simple, they are difficult to explain, because the old ways of thinking
are implicit in the words we use to describe the new thinking. Perhaps the best way to describe the philosophy is to describe
its beginning, with the experience of a 12 year old boy who just had been placed in the first grade.
The boy
was Gene Gendlin. His family had just moved from Austria to North America, and the young boy needed to learn English fast.
Although his new school did not have classes in English as a second language, they did have a first grade teacher who was
supposed to be very good, and who might also have extra time to teach Gene the language of his new country. So at age 12,
he entered a class of six-year-olds and began learning English.
One day,
the teacher noticed that Gene was experiencing the world in German, and then translating into English. For example, he would
see a “stuhl” and then say “chair”. She taught him a simple lesson: that he didn't need to translate,
that what he was looking at could be a “chair” right from the beginning. And when he tried to think in English,
Gene became aware that he had always known what the thing was, independent of the words. In the place of “das stuhl”
there was a familiar “feel” that he had taken for granted until then. He had always known what it was and how
to use it, in a way that didn't depend on words.
As Gendlin
grew older, he noticed this implicit knowing more often, and he began to think more articulately about it. Thus a first grade
teacher launched a 12-year-old boy onto a life-long study of the relationship between language, experiencing, and meaning.
The Implicit
The story
of how a young boy learned English illustrates something very basic about the relationship between language and experiencing.
Language is not a self-contained symbol system. Language functions in a larger context of living interaction with the world.
Because this interaction is us, we “know” it in a very basic way; we “know” what we are doing and
how things are going, without necessarily using words. This preverbal “knowing” is implicit in everything we do.
We don't usually notice it, because we are busy doing other things; but if we look for it, this preverbal “knowing”
can form as a kind of “feel” for what we are doing.
For example,
we routinely do things like driving a car, without thinking about how to do them. At first, it might seem that we don't think
about such things because they are so simple, but in fact the opposite is true. We don't think about them because they are
too intricate to be described in words. Imagine, for example, trying to teach someone over the phone how to drive a car. The
person has never been in a car before, but he has a cell phone, and he is very good at reporting what he sees and following
your instructions; and you are going to explain when and how to change lanes on a crowded interstate.
Even simple
skills like driving are far too complex or intricate for words. But we still know how to do these things, and if we look for
it, we can experience this knowing as a kind of “feel” for what we are doing. This “feel” embodies
huge amount of information, but it isn't conceptual; we don't remember how to walk or drive, we just do it. It's almost as
if our bodies know how to do these things, and we don't.
The example
of driving is hardly unique; most of what we do is like driving. When we talk, we somehow “know” what to say next.
Our words come out with precise grammar, syntax, and meaning; and if one word isn’t quite right, we “feel”
it immediately and correct ourselves. We relate differently to different friends; each relationship has its own rich intricacy,which
could never be described in words, and yet we “know” what to do or say, usually without even thinking. In our
jobs or professions, we have a “feel” for how to solve certain kinds of problems. Living depends on, is,
this larger context of implicit “knowing.”
How is
it possible to do so many complex things without thinking? It is possible because we are alive. Living is a process of ongoing
interaction with the environment, and this process is more basic and more intricate than the process of thinking. A plant
interacts with its environment in ways that humans are only beginning to understand; and yet the plant does this easily without
concepts, or a brain, or even a nervous system. Humans are more complex than plants, and we, too, interact with our environment
in ways that are more intricate than concepts. We breathe, digest food, walk, talk, drive, have relationships, and so on,
without explicit rules; and we don't need explicit rules anymore than the plant does. Most of our living is more intricate
than concepts and goes on quite well without them.
Computers
are a good illustration of this. Because computers can only follow explicit rules, they can teach us a lot about both the
power and the limitations of explicit knowledge. For example, several years ago there was great interest in expert systems.
The idea was to conduct extensive interviews with experts in various fields, and to distill the experts' knowledge into computer
programs. But after years of trying, it became apparent that much of what experts know cannot be expressed in rules. As a
result, we hear very little about expert systems anymore. (cf. Dreyfus, 1992; Dreyfus, H.L., & Dreyfus, S. E., 1986)
Thus, we
“know” more about reality than we can say with concepts, because our living in the world is much more intricate
than concepts.
Relativism
As Gendlin
grew older, he began studying philosophy and he learned that serious errors can result when we try to think without acknowledging
the implicit. For example, at that time (and still today) many people were concerned about relativism. The basic problem is
that all “truths” are the developments of a particular culture and history; so although I might want to believe
that my particular religion, ethics, or science is universally true, it is not hard to find people who have different beliefs
which they think are universally true. Even in science, new ways of thinking cannot be evaluated on purely objective criteria
(Kuhn, 1970). Thus it appears that all beliefs are influenced by culture and history, and “truth” is always relative
to a particular social context.
Gendlin
thought that relativism is correct as far as it goes, but it doesn't go far enough. Certainly, our beliefs are influenced
by where we grew up; but many of our beliefs work reasonably well anyway. We are still able to make airplanes so we can fly
to conferences to talk about relativism.
The problem
with the relativists' argument is that we know more than explicit concepts. We can't conceptualize reality perfectly or completely,
but we are living in it and our living is also a kind of knowing. Of course, anything that can be said explicitly must be
a development of language, culture, and history, and might be said differently in a different context. But language, culture,
history, and concepts all develop from the intricacy of living, and not the other way around.
For example,
our concepts about why things fall has changed significantly over the last few centuries: In 1400, things fell because the
elements earth and water “wanted” to go down; in 1700, they fell because of gravity; in the 1900s, they fell because
of space-time curvature, and later because of gravitons. But as the explicit “truth” changes due to culture and
history, things continue to fall.
This example
points to something which is very basic, and difficult to say in words. Concepts like gravity are indeed developments of culture
and history, but that means that they are also developments of our living in the world. The process of living is an ongoing
interaction, an intricate “knowing” of the world that is validated by the fact that we go on living. If there
were no order, if everything was chaos, we would die. The fact that concepts always change, but we go on living, demonstrates
an implicit order that is more than our concepts. Gendlin would call this order the Implicit Intricacy, or The Responsive Order (Gendlin, 1997).
Although
basic to living, implicit knowing is often overlooked precisely because it is implicit. If we're not aware of it, and we can't
say it in words, then it doesn't seem like real knowledge. Gendlin would explore this problem further, but he already knew
that implicit knowing doesn't have to be outside awareness. He knew that if we look for it, this knowing appears as a kind
of “feel” for different situations, people, or things. And because it is so much richer than explicit concepts,
this “feel” can be extremely useful in many situations. For example, Einstein wrote that as he worked on his general
theory of relativity over 15 years, he was guided by a “feeling” for what the eventual solution would be.
These considerations
led to a major discovery, and an unlikely digression in Gendlin's career.
Psychotherapy
Gendlin
entered the graduate program in philosophy at the University of Chicago because he wanted to learn to think more clearly about
the Implicit Intricacy; but when he tried to talk about it, no one there seemed to understand him. The problem, he realized,
was that they were all absorbed in explicit concepts. When everything is either a “stuhl” or a “chair,”
so to speak, we don't attend to the Implicit.
Gendlin
thought that people who were questioning their basic understanding of the world, might also be more aware of the Implicit.
But where could he find such people? He guessed that people who were questioning at a deep level might be in emotional distress,
and might be in therapy. At that time, Carl Rogers was in charge of the Counseling Center at the University of Chicago. So
one day, the originator of Client-Centered Therapy received a visit from a philosophy student. This student had no background
in psychology, but he wanted to join Roger's clinic and be trained as a psychotherapist. Rogers agreed.
It was
the beginning of a long and fruitful collaboration. Working with others on Roger's team, Gendlin showed that some psychotherapy
clients do indeed refer to something beyond words, and that this referring could be reliably measured (Gendlin, E. T., Beebe,
J., Cassens, J., Klein, M., & Oberlander, M., 1968). When clients referred to this “something,” they experienced
it as a “feel” or bodily awareness, which Gendlin called a felt sense. This felt sense was not a feeling
like anger or sadness, but the intricate and preconceptual “knowing” that we all have of different situations.
Not surprisingly, this awareness turned out to be extremely useful in psychotherapy: Gendlin found that the degree to which
people referred to their felt sense in the first two sessions of therapy correlated with the ultimate success of therapy
one or two years later! (This remarkable finding has been replicated 27 times since then; Hendricks, 2002).
But this
latter finding raised a disturbing question: if you could tell after two sessions that someone wouldn't benefit from therapy,
was it ethical to allow them to continue? Gendlin answered the question with further research. Together with co-workers, he
found that clients could learn felt sense awareness, and he developed a procedure to teach it. Gendlin's procedure, which
he called Focusing, has turned out to be extremely useful. Numerous studies have shown that felt sense awareness improves
therapy outcome, and this finding holds across many forms of therapy and across a variety of cultures (Hendricks, 2002). Focusing is also useful outside of therapy; today it is practiced in 29 countries worldwide by thousands of people who are not in therapy, but who find it helpful in areas ranging from sports, to creative writing, to business. Gendlin's book, Focusing, has sold over 400,000 copies and is printed in twelve languages.
In recognition
of this work, Gendlin the philosopher was the first person to receive the Distinguished Psychologist of the Year award from
the American Psychological Association. He also founded and edited a major psychological journal, and received other awards
from the American Psychological Association.
But in
spite of this recognition, Gendlin's work was widely misunderstood. In particular, focusing is often misunderstood as a way
to “get in touch with your feelings”. The reason for this misunderstanding is interesting. It has to do with the
relationship between explicit concepts and implicit knowing; and in particular, with an implicit way of thinking that influences
many of our explicit concepts.
The Unit Model
Over the
last few hundred years, our understanding of the world has been strongly influenced by a mathematical way of thinking that
Gendlin calls the unit model. Mathematics is a very useful and powerful way of thinking, and it works because numbers
have certain properties. Over many years, and particularly since the scientific revolution, the success of mathematical thinking
has led us to ascribe mathematical properties to the world.. At first, this was done heuristically, with an “as if”
attitude (by Descartes, for example). But over hundreds of years, this way of thinking has been so successful that today it
has acquired the status of common sense.
Gendlin
describes the unit model in some detail; but stated simply, it involves two related assumptions. First, the unit model assumes
the world is composed of separately existing units. In other words, units have separate identities which remain the same regardless
of how they are moved around and combined. Secondly, the unit model assumes that units are inanimate. Units don't have their
own desires and can't do whatever they want; instead, their behavior is determined by extrinsic causes, such as laws of nature.
Together,
these two assumptions give us a very powerful way to think about the world; modern science and technology are living testimony
to the power of this approach. And over hundreds of years, the continuing success of science has led both scientists and lay
people to assume that the universe really is composed of separate inanimate parts. The unit model has become second nature
to us, intuitively obvious. Today we often think of the unit model, not as an hypothesis, but as how things really are.
For this
reason, it's good to remember that the unit model wasn't always intuitively obvious. It took the smartest minds in Europe
many hundreds of years to create it, and they initially considered it a heuristic way of thinking, not a description of reality.
It's
also good to remember that it is problematic to judge any theory on its supposed correspondence with reality. First of all,
we don't have any independent to measuring reality. Moreover, the history of science is a history of change that gives us
no reason to think that any concept, theory, or model will remain true forever. But we can still judge the unit model's validity
from what we can do with it, and by that measure it is very useful and very valid. But in spite of its usefulness, the unit
model has serious limitations.
Misapplying the Unit Model to Life
In particular,
the unit model offers a very limited way of thinking about life. For example, living things are not made of separate inanimate
parts. We can measure the human body in units and describe various parts, but this is just a simple way of conceptualizing
something much more intricate.
The digestive
system, for example, isn't actually a separate entity. First of all, it is a process in which no “parts” stay
the same; for example, new cells are constantly being created as old ones die. Further, the cells of the digestive system
are in constant interaction with the rest of the body, so we would say in unit model terms that the digestive system involves
many other systems; the nervous system, immune system, cell metabolism, endocrine system, and many more. But each of those
systems involves the digestive system.
What
we call different systems are really aspects of one living process, a human being. Different systems are identified by an
observer, depending on that observer's interests; thus different anatomy charts actually divide the body up differently, depending
on which system they are describing. Moreover, an observer can discover new systems by looking at the body in some new way.
For example, our sense of psychological well being has a certain continuity and it both affects and is affected by other systems.
So we might say we have discovered a new system, psychological well being; and we might study how that system affects other
systems like digestion, and how those systems affect it. There is no objective determination regarding which systems exist
and where their boundaries lie, because the determination depends in part on the interests and purposes of a human observer.
We are the observer, and we are part of the process; so how we describe the process (what concepts we use, what systems we
discover) will change according to our goals and purposes.
The issue
of goals and purposes points to another limitation of the unit model when applied to life. Life is active, it is always in
the midst of a next step. The next step could be photosynthesis, hunting for food, building a career, or finding the meaning
of life; but it is always happening. Further, the next step is not a specific thing but a way forward. If one way forward
is blocked, life finds another way, or it dies. What counts as a way forward and what doesn't emerges from the organism's
ongoing interaction with the Implicit Intricacy; it is therefore more intricate than concepts, and cannot be formulated explicitly
or specified in advance. It is implied.
Living
is a continuous implying. For example, if you try walking in a natural way, each "part" of the process implies the
next "part," so that if you try to freeze at any point, you risk falling over. An observer could think of walking as a series
of separate “parts”; but such “parts” would have little in common with unit model parts. In the unit
model, parts exist separately and are related by external causes; but in living (walking for example), “parts”
exist only together, and their relationship or organization is formed internally by their implying of each other and of the
next step in the process.
In short,
living things have important qualities that cannot be described in unit model terms. This does not make the unit model invalid,
it only means that the unit model is a way of thinking and that it isn't real in any ultimate sense. In Gendlin's terms, the
Implicit Intricacy is always more than concepts; that is why science is always changing. So the problem is not in the unit
model; the problem is in the fallacious assumption that if something can be measured in units, it is actually made of units.
A Paradox and its Consequences
Zeno
illustrated this fallacy 2500 years ago with his dichotomy paradox: For an arrow to reach its target, it must first traverse
half the distance between the archer and the target, then half the remaining distance, half of that distance, and so on to
infinity. No matter how small the half distances become, it will take the arrow a certain amount of time to cross each one;
but because the number of half-distances is infinite, the arrow will need an infinite amount of time to cross all of them.
Therefore, the arrow can never reach its target.
Of
course, Zeno's argument never convinced anyone that arrows don't reach their targets. Because we know arrows reach their targets,
we know something must be wrong with the argument; and we quickly see that the problem is a misapplication of the unit model.
Even though we can measure the arrow's path in units, it is not actually made of units. The units are a useful way of thinking,
but they aren't real. So the distance between the archer and the target remains whole and unchanged no matter how many times
we divide it, and the arrow reaches its target unaffected by our measurements.
It
is easy to see the faulty assumption in Zeno's dichotomy paradox; but consider what happens when the same erroneous assumption
is presented in a different way. First, instead of applying the unit model to a span of distance, apply it to people: Assume
that human beings are a collection of inanimate parts subject to deterministic laws of science. By definition, such inanimate
parts don't have consciousness or volition. Therefore, we are impossible.
If
we suspected the unit model when it “proved” arrows don't reach their targets, we should be even more suspicious
when it “proves” we are impossible. But instead, we have struggled for hundreds of years with a series of related
paradoxes with names like “free will vs. determinism” and “the mind/body problem.” Instead of questioning
the unit model, we try to solve these modern versions of Zeno's Paradox by applying it ever more carefully; by trying to create
“scientific” explanations of consciousness, for example. But the unit model is fundamentally unable to deal with
such issues; attempts to find "the ghost in the machine" must always fail, because machines by their nature exclude ghosts.
Unfortunately,
our uncritical application of the unit model to ourselves also has more serious consequences. The unit model encourages us
to think of ourselves as objects; for example, to think of the body as "a wonderful machine," or the brain as a computer.
When we think of ourselves as machines, and living as some (as yet unexplained) mechanistic process, then human value and
meaning seem like illusions, or worse, variables to be measured and manipulated. As values erode, we become increasingly cynical
and materialistic. We develop scientific techniques to study and manipulate employees, consumers, and political constituents.
With nothing higher to reach for, we seek meaning and identity in what we own. Social cohesion breaks down and we become passive
consumers, disconnected from each other, just as the unit model described.
It
is difficult to break out of this process if we assume that the unit model is a description of reality, rather than just a
useful way of thinking. If we assume that everything is made of separate inanimate parts, we must assume that “everything”
includes us. And to the extent that we are sure of our concepts, we tend to overlook those aspects of experiencing that our
concepts leave out. The unit model tells us who we are, and to our detriment, we believe it. In the words of Allan Bloom (1987),
“progress culminates in the recognition that life is meaningless.”
A New Way of Thinking
The
key to this problem lies in the lesson Gendlin learned from his first grade teacher. There is an intricate experiencing, not
only behind words like “chair” or “stuhl,” but also also behind concepts and conceptual systems. Models
are just models; they are not reality, even when they work extremely well. Good models make everything seem very precise,
but there is always a great deal more in experiencing that remains implicit.
It
is easy to accept concepts as more real than experiencing; the history of science is filled with examples of smart, dedicated
people who ignored phenomena that didn't fit their preconceptions. We can't afford to do this with the unit model any longer,
because what the unit model leaves out is too important.
We
need a new way of thinking. We need to think about the full intricacy of life, including ourselves, in ways that are not reductionistic.
But this is not easy. Because the intricacy of living is greater than concepts, any conceptual model would leave out some
aspect of the intricacy of life. For this reason, we need more than just a new set of concepts. We need a new way of thinking,
a way that somehow includes what concepts leave out. In other words, we need to think in a way that includes the Implicit.
That alone would be hard enough; it’s difficult to even think of implying as an entity. But as we think with the Implicit,
we also need to keep the precision of the unit model, because vague concepts do not advance understanding.
There were
good reasons to think this was impossible. On one level, it was always assumed that that whatever doesn't fit our concepts
is necessarily too vague or chaotic for conceptual analysis. For example, we use words like “emotion,” “intuition,”
or “inspiration” to describe writing a poem or falling in love. No one has been able to conceptualize such experiences
without being reductionistic, and because they couldn't be conceptualized, such experiences were considered off limits for
systematic inquiry. But this is just one aspect of an even deeper problem. As we saw, it is the nature of living things that
they imply a next step; so if we are going to think about living, we're going to have to think about implying. But unlike
love or poetry, implying isn't even a thing we can point to; it is a kind of movement toward something unspecified. Because
implying is implicit, it appeared to be out of bounds for clear, explicit thinking.
In
short, it had always been assumed that precisely cut and defined entities are the basis for precise thinking. This assumption
has been very costly, because it has meant the most important aspects of human existence—values, purpose in life, love,
spirituality, even living itself—were too vague and “subjective” for precise thinking. But the assumption
turned out to be wrong.
As a philosopher,
Gendlin understood kinds of concepts in the same way that architects understand kinds of buildings. Knowing
the strengths and limitations of different kinds of concepts, Gendlin designed a new way of thinking, new concepts, and a
new model.
The Philosophy of the Implicit
Gendlin
described this new way of thinking in his book Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning (paperback edition 1977). Among other things, he showed that concepts have a structure that is derived from implying,
and that there is an orderly but more-than-logical relationship between concepts and the Implicit. This made it possible to
develop a method for concepts to interact with the Implicit, so that concepts can retain and even increase their precision,
while changing in a systematic way to include aspects of the Intricacy that had been left out.
Then, in
A Process Model, Gendlin (1997) showed how this new method can be used, by creating an alternative to the unit model. A Process Model
develops a single coherent set of concepts that are derived from the experience of living, instead of from mathematics. Radically
different from the unit model, the Process Model develops concepts to think about life; the new concepts are very precise
yet widely applicable, offering useful and researchable insights into numerous problems such as the evolution of life, the
nature of language, the incompatibility of relativity theory and quantum physics, and the nature of spiritual experience.
Like any
seminal model, A Process Model invites a new kind of experiencing. In the words of one reader, “It is no exaggeration
to say that my sense of who and what I am, and what the universe is, has radically changed in a beautiful and exciting way.”
But Gendlin believes that his most important contribution is not the concepts themselves, but how they were derived. He repeatedly
advises his readers not to accept A Process Model as truth. He intends this book as a demonstration of his new
method of thinking, and he predicts that better models will be developed in the future.
Because
Gendlin's method and the resulting concepts really are new, Western readers find them difficult to grasp (although it is interesting
that Gendlin has a large following in Japan, where his method and concepts seem to be more in tune with the traditional culture and philosophy. Gendlin asks us to
make a shift comparable to the shift from the medieval to the scientific world-view (c.f. Kuhn, 1970). But although it is
hard work, making the shift is enormously rewarding because it enables us to think in new and productive ways about science,
spirituality, and life.
More importantly,
it enables us to use concepts in a new way. We don't have to think with just one model, and be trapped by its limitations.
Because there is an orderly relationship between concepts and the Implicit, we can use concepts in a precise and systematic
way that includes the Implicit. By including the Implicit, we can use different models, taking what is useful in each, without
being bound by its limitations. As Gendlin learned when he was 12, everything doesn't have to be just a “stuhl”
or just a “chair.” We don't have to translate anymore.
Practical Applications
Gendlin
has published over 240 professional articles and books. His philosophy cannot be described easily, but some of its applications
can.
-
Focusing is a teachable procedure that anyone can
use to access the deeper, implicit knowing that comes with having lived with a problem or situation. Originally intended to
help clients do better in psychotherapy, it is now used by thousands of non-therapists around the world.
-
Spirituality: Gendlin invites us to explore
beyond our usual concepts, whether they be concepts of religious belief or of atheism. He wants to evoke in his readers
the actual basis for spiritual experience, the Implicit itself. We may use spiritual language here if we want, but it
isn't necessary. We point to the experience with whatever words work best.
Focusing, in particular, has helped many people discover or deepen the spiritual dimension
of their lives. By its nature, Focusing invites people to live their spirituality in very immediate and practical ways; for example, as spiritual awareness deepens, words and rituals that had seemed completely empty for many years,
suddenly open up into whole new worlds of meaning.
Focusing is currently being used in a variety of religious traditions,
including Judaism, Christianity, Buddhism, Zen Buddhism, and Islam. For example, Focusing is currently being used in Pakistan and Afghanistan to help aid workers and trauma survivors; practitioners find that it integrates beautifully
with their practice of Islam. Additional information is available on the Focusing Institute's Spirituality web page.
-
Thinking at the Edge (TAE) is a way of developing implicit knowing into an articulate theory. For
example, a professional might have an inchoate felt sense about a technical problem. Using TAE, one can articulate this implicit
knowledge and use it to generate explicit concepts, or even a formal theory, that others can use. TAE is currently being taught
and applied in a variety of settings ranging from business to psychotherapy.
-
Research: In addition to research already completed
in fields like psychotherapy (Hendricks, 2002) and education (Zimring 1983, 1985; Zimring & Katz, 1988), Gendlin's philosophy presents
profound and researchable challenges to conventional thinking in fields as diverse as genetics (Gendlin, 1997, pp. 882-3),
physics (Gendlin, E.T. & J. Lemke, 1983), linguistics and anthropology (Gendlin, 1997, pp. 122-215).
-
Changing the materialistic world-view: Materialistic
science pervades our thinking, with negative effects. Gendlin's philosophy challenges this at all levels. For example, in
A Process Model, Gendlin criticized the neo-Darwinian theory of evolution by showing that life could not
have evolved only passively and mechanistically, and he predicted that other specific processes must be involved. When the
first edition of A Process Model
came out in 1981, Gendlin's claim seemed outrageous. Today, Gendlin's view is beginning to receive empirical support as researchers
discover that under stressful conditions, organisms appear to participate actively in their own evolution (e.g., Ben-Jacob, E., 1998; Lolle et al., 2005).
Major Writings
Gendlin
has over 240 publications. His two major philosophical works are Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning, which develops explicit ways of approaching the Implicit; and A Process Model, which demonstrates this method by developing a body of consistent concepts for thinking about living process, with implications
for our thinking about space, time, science, genetics, ethology, consciousness, language, and spirituality.
Gendlin's
other major works include:
References
Ben-Jacob, E. (1998). Bacterial wisdom, Godel's theorem and creative genomic webs. Physica A 248, 57-76.
Ben-Jacob, E., Aharonov, Y., & Shapira, Y. (2004).
Bacteria harnessing complexity. Biofilms 1, 239–263 (doi:10.1017/S1479050505001596)
Ben-Jacob, E., & Levine, H. (2005). Self-engineering capabilities of bacteria. J. R. Soc. Interface (doi:10.1098/rsif.2005.0089) Published online
Ben-Jacob, E., & Shapira, Y. (in press). Meaning-based natural intelligence vs. information-based artificial intelligence. In Cradle of Creativity (2005).
Ben-Jacob, E., Shapira, Y., & Tauber, A. I. (2006). Seeking the foundations of cognition in bacteria: From Schrödinger's Negative Entropy to Latent Information. Physica A vol 359 ; 495-524.
Dreyfus, H. L. (1992). What computers still can’t
do: a critique of artificial reason. London: MIT Press.
Dreyfus, H.L., & Dreyfus, S. E. (1986). Mind over
machine. New York: The Free Press.
Gendlin, E.T. (1962). Experiencing and the creation of meaning. A philosophical and psychological approach to the subjective. New York: Free Press of Glencoe. (Reprinted by Macmillan, 1970; reprinted in paperback by Northwestern
University Press, 1997)
Gendlin, E.T. (1991). Crossing and dipping: some terms for approaching the interface between natural
understanding and logical formulation. In M. Galbraith & W.J. Rapaport (Eds.), Subjectivity and the debate over computational cognitive science, pp. 37-59. Buffalo: State University of New York. Reprinted
in Minds and Machines, 1995, 5 (4),
547-560.
Gendlin, E.T. (1991). Thinking beyond patterns: body, language and situations. In B. den Ouden & M. Moen (Eds.), The presence of feeling in thought, pp. 25-151.
New York: Peter Lang.
Gendlin, E.T. (1992). The primacy of the body, not the primacy of perception. Man and
World, 25 (3-4), 341-353.
Gendlin, E. T. (1997). A process model. New York: The Focusing Institute
Gendlin, E.T. (1997). How philosophy cannot appeal to experience, and how it can. In D.M. Levin (Ed.),
Language beyond postmodernism: Saying and thinking in Gendlin's philosophy, pp. 3-41 & 343. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Gendlin, E.T. (1997). The responsive order: A new empiricism. Man and World, 30
(3), 383-411.
Gendlin, E. T. (2004). An Introduction to Thinking at the Edge. The Folio, 19 (1)
Gendlin, E. T., Beebe, J., Cassens, J., Klein, M., & Oberlander, M. (1968). Focusing ability in psychotherapy, personality, and creativity. In
J.M. Shlien (Ed.), 1968. Research in psychotherapy. Vol. III, pp. 217-241. Washington, DC: APA.
Gendlin, E.T. & Lemke, J. (1983). A critique of relativity and localization. Mathematical Modelling, 4, 61-72.
Hendricks, M. N. (2002). Focusing-oriented/experiential psychotherapy. In Cain, David and Seeman, Jules (Eds.) Humanistic
Psychotherapies: Handbook of Research and Practice (pp. 221-251). Washington,
DC: American Psychological Association.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lolle, S. J., Victor, J. L., Young, J. M. and Pruitt, R. E. (2005). Genome-wide non-mendelian inheritance
of extra-genomic information in Arabidopsis. Nature, 434,
505–509.
Zimring,
F. R. (1983). Attending to feelings and cognitive performance. Journal of Research
and Personality, 17 (3) 288-299.
Zimring,
F. R. (1985). The effect of attending to feeling on memory for internally generated stimuli. Journal of Research and Personality, 19 (2) 170-184.
Zimring,
F. R., & Katz, K. (1988). Self-focus and relational knowledge. Journal of
Research and Personality, 22 (3) 273-289.